Blog Archives

It’s not just humans who use medicines or are drawn to wild plants to cure ailments. Animals are
known to self-medicate when they are ill, wounded or for stress and sadness. This
phenomenon, known as Zoopharmacognosy, has been observed in many species of animals. It
reveals how animals interact with their environment in a way people have written off as
exclusive to human science and medicine.

One common example is when dogs and cats eat grass to induce vomiting. There are many
other examples of animals using medicine in sophisticated ways. For example, apes have been
observed isolating the medicinal parts of plants by tearing off leaves and stems and taking them
internally or applying the pant to their wounds. Research in lambs has shown that animals can
learn to use medicine by observing the effects of certain plant foods. Animals eat plants to expel
parasites, get nutrients missing from their diets, and induce labor, among other things.

An Indonesian male orangutan named Rakus was observed applying plant sap and crushed
leaves to a wound on the “flange” surrounding his face, as a poultice. The plant, known locally
as akar kuning (Fibraurea tinctoria), is an Asian plant known for its antibacterial, antifungal, anti-
inflammatory and pain relief properties. Rakus was applying plant medication externally for
healing in the same manner that humans used this traditional medicine.

Andrea DiGiorgio, a biological anthropologist at Princeton University, noted that animals don’t
need to understand everything about the medicinal properties of a plant to be able to utilize the
resources in their environment in an intelligent way. DiGiorgio said: “I think this really speaks to
the intelligence that all animals have to utilize what works for them.”

Humans assume that the taxonomy of human knowledge accumulated through language and
writing gives us superior intelligence and understanding of our environment, but this speaks to
the advantages of human technological development rather than intelligence itself. This is
called Speciesism; and carries with the idea that humans are at the top of the hierarchy and
have the greater moral value.

Animal intelligence is rich and in tune with its environment. Often humans are looking in the
wrong places when they search for animal intelligence and knowledge, basing it on concepts of
intelligence that have been imposed by human and Western perspectives. If we observe
animals in their environment, we can see what we have missed. Animals often lead humans to
medicinal plants, water and shelter. Their remarkable senses and intelligence are not
meaningless tools that assist human technology, they should be respected in their own right.

|
No Comments

The FDA is finally catching up with animal rights advocates. A new law signed by President Biden at the end of December reflects the reality that testing on animals is cruel, and – ironically – unscientific. The FDA Modernization Act 2.0 ends the requirement that drugs in development must undergo testing in animals before being given to participants in human trials. 

Animal Testing is Unreliable

Animal testing has been found to be an unreliable predictor of toxicity in a large range of drugs. The FDA Modernization Act makes way for new methods of animal testing such as testing cells grown on chips, or organoids, organized cell tissue mimicking human organs. Data modeling has also been shown to help predict human reactions to drugs. Animal testing is a slow and tortuous process. The lab animal trade imports animals like monkeys into the US to be caged and tested by being implanted with diseases like cancer. The suffering the animals endure is intense and unconscionable. In our recent blog, we discussed how Elon Musk’s Neuralink has been using rhesus macaques in botched experiments that have caused painful injury and death. The “forward thinking” company has been needlessly killing animals and operating under a “move fast and break things” policy which has resulted in animal suffering more than it has produced results. 

Animal Suffering is Not Yet Over

The FDA Modernization Act does not yet make animal testing illegal. There is a long way to go before the suffering of lab animals is over. It’s estimated that around 50 million animals are used in lab experiments in the US each year. A large majority of the animals are highly intelligent and social animals who can understand what’s happening to them and witness the suffering of their peers. 

What You Can Do 

The FDA’s New Law makes it more likely that states will move to ban animal testing on cosmetics and more, as New York just did. It’s important to maintain pressure on local representatives to change the law. You can also help by boycotting all companies that test their products on animals. Apps such as “cruelty cutter” and “Bunny” can help you to vet the products you are buying to check if they are cruelty free. 

 

|
No Comments

Elon Musk is not exactly the world’s most liked figure. One more reason for negative publicity is the revelation that Neuralink, a startup Musk founded in 2016, has killed 1,500 animals since 2018. Allegedly many of the animals suffered horribly from botched experiments.

The animals in question are rhesus macaques who were undergoing experiments by the company to develop a brain chip implant that Neuralink claims could one day help paralyzed people to walk and blind people to see. Beyond the dazzling scientific pitch for this device, there are horrific reports of animals who had their skulls breached to implant the experimental device, and in one case (according to public records) gaps in an animal’s skull were filled with an unapproved adhesive which caused the animal to hemorrhage. In another case a monkey had nausea so severe she had open sores on her esophagus before she was killed. Animals suffered from chronic staph and other infections after having the brain chip implanted.

Other evidence for this horrific treatment is an impassioned internal letter written by an employee concerned about the need to slow down the pace to avoid “hack jobs” on the animals during the experimental surgery. The “break things and move fast” speed has been blamed for the company’s cruel and cavalier treatment of animals. Elon Musk apparently told employees at Neuralink to work “as if they had a bomb strapped to their head.”

The USDA Inspector General has opened a probe into potential Animal Welfare Act violations at Neuralink. This is not a common occurrence, as research standards are often left to institutional Animal Care and Research bodies at universities. The Animal Welfare Act doesn’t adequately protect many animals in the first place. Companion animals and other animals held in captivity have more protection than animals used in agriculture, mice and rats. Overall protections for animals used in research are inadequate.

The USDA probe suggests something has gone horribly wrong with the treatment of animals at Neuralink. Animals have become a casualty not only of a culture that disregards animals, but also of a capitalist, disposable culture of speed and greed.

Animal rights will never be a concern so long as we live in a culture where meeting production schedules are more valuable than life. In this culture, everyone is the product – whether it’s humans or defenseless research animals. Because animals can’t speak for themselves, we allow the abuse of research animals to continue. Paying attention to stories like this can help us stay alert to the violent realities of animal research and hold everyone involved accountable.

|
No Comments

Giving animals, trees and rivers legal rights is no longer a fringe idea. The Law Society, the professional body for solicitors in England and Wales, has produced a report that says that granting legal rights and protections to non-human entities such as animals, trees and rivers is critical if nations are to confront climate collapse and the collapse of habitat and biodiversity.

The report is called Law in the Emerging Bio Age. The title indicates the big shift in thinking when it comes to humanity’s view of our place in our environment alongside other creatures. The idea that we live in the “bio age” is correct. Humans can no longer rely on the conceptual framework of the Western Christian tradition, in which we are outside nature and have dominion over nature. This attitude has brought us to the brink of the extinction of our species. It has destroyed whole species in the great age of extinction caused by pollution and human activity.

It’s time to move beyond the destructive power of exploitative traditions that inform our law and our societies. We can look to societies and nations that are informed by indigenous traditions for inspiration. Ecuador for example, has enshrined legal rights for the natural world, based on the tradition of respecting the earth mother goddess, Pachamama. Bolivia has also granted rights to nature. New Zealand has granted personhood to a former National Park, Te Urewara Park, the Whanganui river and Mt Taranaki.

In the West, in certain countries and states, the law has started to consider that animals should be defined as people rather than property in divorce cases.

These changes represent promising new seeds, but more has to be done to protect the vast swathes of the earth and its creatures that are vulnerable to human exploitation. It is time to accept that we live in the “bio age,” and time to build a new legal and political framework to legislate for our connectedness to natural and animal life.

Read More:

https://vjel.vermontlaw.edu/rights-nature-movement-closer-look-new-zealand#:~:text=Rather%20than%20incorporate%20a%20rights,Taranaki.

https://www.theguardian.com/environment/2022/oct/10/give-legal-rights-to-animals-trees-and-rivers-say-experts

|
No Comments

Last year when the world was struggling to find a solution to the global COVID-19 pandemic, researchers who were testing on animals moved quickly to human trials and conducted some of the fastest ever research using human trials. The vaccines were ready for rollout 6 months later.

This is not a normal timeline. Usually, animals are tested on and suffer for years in clinical trials before drugs and treatments are deemed safe to test on humans. Yet in 2020, somehow it was possible to speed up development and cut out years of animal suffering.

Also in 2020, animal testing dragged on even though the vaccines were showing promising results in humans. There was a “monkey shortage,” as labs rushed to perform unnecessary tests on rhesus macaques who were imported over great distances to suffer in labs and then be euthanized.

Over 100 million animals die during animal tests every year according to PETA. One reason so many animals are killed in the US is that animal testing is simply a bureaucratic requirement to receive drug approval, according to this blog.

And of course, animal testing is also big business. The demand for animals in research is subject to predictions and betting about how much money it’s worth, just like any other market. The so-called “monkey shortage” is yet another way humans reveal the value they place on animal life. Animals are a commodity to serve humans, not living beings.

PETA has an informative list of reasons why animal tests are unnecessary and cruel. One of the reasons is the abject failure of many treatments and drugs tested on animals when they are tested on humans. It is an inexact science to compare human and animal biological systems, and some of these tests even harm humans. The thinking seems to be to just throw any research at the problem and see if it sticks. The excuse for being able to do things this way is the underlying belief that animals are disposable.

Please check out this PETA list of reasons why animal testing isn’t necessary and why other testing methods are becoming the norm: https://headlines.peta.org/end-experiments-on-animals-for-covid-19/

Read More:

https://www.bignewsnetwork.com/news/268699398/animal-model-market-driven-by-developments-in-pharmaceutical-and-crispr-genetic-research-opines-factmr

https://insidesources.com/there-is-no-monkey-shortage-for-covid-19-research-because-no-monkeys-are-needed/

https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/health/2020/09/10/covid-vaccine-treatment-trials-create-monkey-shortage-science/5714115002/

|
No Comments

Just as the world’s most recent ape species was discovered, their habitat is about to be decimated. The Northern Sumatran Tanpanuli Orangutan was only discovered last year, and the population is already known to be the most endangered ape species in the world. The orangutans are threatened by Chinese diggers constructing a hydroelectric dam that will divide their habitat in two.

The dam has been opposed by leading environmentalists. Research in top scientific journals has shown that its impact will be disastrous. Yet it still goes ahead because of an injection of funding from the Chinese State Bank. Other major funders have pulled money based on the impacts on the orangutans, amongst other things. The reason why this disastrous project is being protected is that it is part of a huge Chinese plan for infrastructure to facilitate trade. Projects like this will spring up elsewhere, harming other wildlife.

Videos show orangutans clawing at diggers who are moving into their habitat. Orangutan literally means “man of the forest.” We must stop the advance of human works of such magnitude and harm. The vulnerable are counting on us. Please sign and share.

See Also:

https://news.mongabay.com/2018/07/scientists-urge-indonesian-president-to-nix-dam-in-orangutan-habitat/

https://www.theguardian.com/environment/radical-conservation/2018/apr/23/worlds-newest-great-ape-threatened-by-chinese-dam

|
No Comments

This last week, the world has been in mourning for Koko the beloved mountain gorilla who learned to speak in American sign language. Koko was born on the 4th of July 1971, hence her name “Fireworks-child” (in Japanese), shortened to “Koko.” This fireworks child was a prodigy – she learned to play the recorder, and to sign over 1,000 signs and understand 2,000 words of spoken English. Koko was sad when she lost a pet, spoke about her longing for a child (the pet kitten was a close substitute) and talked about death and her own death. She also played with words and mixed them up in new combinations. She once described herself as a “fine-gorilla-person.”

Did humans teach Koko about language, or did Koko teach humans? Koko could speak in sign language,
but also more importantly, she could listen. When she listened, she interpreted things in her own way.
Despite criticism of the Koko project (which stated that Koko was mimicking her trainers), Koko
responded in unexpected ways. When she was asked where gorillas go to when they die, she said
“comfortable-hole-bye.” There were a few occasions when she expressed deep sadness and grief, like
when her pet kitten was hit by a car and killed.

Language is often used as an excuse to elevate humans above other animals. There were scientists who
felt Koko’s use of language was meaningless, as she didn’t learn grammar and syntax. But throughout
her life, Koko used sign language not as a lifeless toy or tool to get food and water, but a way to
communicate and describe her world. Communication –- rather than language –- was the key. Koko
and her researchers built a rapport together, where words could mean more than the dictionary
definition, they could mean complex emotional states and refer to shared understanding between
Koko and the researchers. Above all, what Koko taught us is that language is a human invention, but
communication is common to all animals. For that, we owe a debt to Koko, our Gorilla teacher.

|
No Comments

As foundation to a new approach to the moral life, it is important not only to do the right thing but also to have good dispositions, motivations, attitudes, character, and moral habit. It goes beyond the duties of the law and motivates people toward excellence. The overall goal is for humans to go beyond mere survival and to flourish together in communities. This sought after state of eudaimonia requires social institutions that work for justice and fairness. This infrastructure creates the environmental conditions that allow for the individuals within it to excel.

Once we figure out which character traits we ought to cultivate then we must consistently incorporate them into our occupational and personal lives. When we acquire these dispositions we must then learn how to apply them to the right degree. That is, in our experience of such states as fear, anxiety, anger, and so forth, we must learn to experience them at the right time, toward the right objects, toward the right people, for the right reason and in the right manner, applying a standard of balance. What is very important is that we emulate those of us who have developed virtuous behavior. Correspondingly, when we act virtuously we must serve as exemplars for others in our communities.

In order to figure out which of the virtues we ought to focus on and develop, we must first understand our values as an organization or as a community, for it is these values that virtuous behavior must serve. Let us understand that a value is an ideal or something that we aspire toward as a state of being or a condition. In contrast, a virtue is a behavior that supports the value. A partial list of possible virtues could include the following ones: unity, identity, democracy, integrity, family, community, hard work, and strength. Let’s briefly define them.

Unity means a kind of solidarity in which we come together to advance the dignity of each of us, and all of us together.  This does not seem to be the type of system that has emerged from the Enlightenment and its valorization of autonomy.  As a part of this solidarity we must acknowledge the identity of each individual and group of individuals. To further the value of identity, we must also value democracy, for in this kind of system we respect diversity, our responsibility to it as well as to the democratic process. Integrity implies unwavering commitment. Hard work and strength imply assiduousness, focus, and perseverance.  Further, there are many ways to talk about this list of values and their corresponding virtues. We must focus here, though, on how this cluster of values comes together to form what we are as moral selves. While keeping the preceding list in mind, let’s focus on three major values as well as related values that support the major ones. The major values that we want to address are solidarity, justice, and responsibility. The supporting values include integrity, respect for others, beneficence, and compassion.

The primordial condition of solidarity is that the other is entrusted to me in an unconditional manner. We are similarly situated, with similar pain, and similar challenges. It is a belonging together that emerges from the realization that the community one belongs to constitutes a single whole. It is a state of interdependence, an ethical feeling of compassion, and a deep spiritual connection. On the sociological level, for example in any community, group, or organization, we are dependent upon each other, not only for our survival but for our flourishing as well. On the personal level this requires us to be empathic or compassionate with each other, to stand in each other’s shoes. This requires us to commit ourselves to the common good and to the good of each individual because each of us is responsible for all. Even more, it requires radical selflessness and forgiveness of each other. It presupposes a symmetrical relation of respect for each other’s rights, as well as an asymmetrical relation that goes beyond rights. This asymmetry requires self-sacrifice. Thus, the needs of the other take priority over one’s own interests.

Solidarity requires us to go beyond the contractual model to a social model that is based on covenant. In this model, every relationship that is mediated by objects, including capital and property, must be subordinated to the more fundamental relationship between people as communal beings–that is, we need each other. The quality of the relationship of solidarity is an end in itself, a state in which we overcome the valuation of others for extrinsic, instrumental reasons. This is linked to the axiom that there is a universal right to use the resources of the earth. Thus, based on the assumption of the individual dignity of each person, each of us must be seen in a way such that individual interests must never run counter to the general welfare. That is, the universal goods of the union are to be shared universally. This requires those of us with more shared goods to share them with the less fortunate. This process should humanize our contractual relations.  In my trans-humanist account, we must also take into account the equal dignity of all living things.  We must limit our use of the earth’s resources by the interests of all Others as I will explain.

The process of contributing to this state of solidarity triggers the value of justice. Justice is fairness. It is the principle of moral rightness. It is the upholding of what is just, especially fair treatment and due reward. In valuing justice, then, we are committed to the fair and equitable treatment of persons. Justice entails rewarding persons in accordance with their deserts, or withholding the reward when appropriate. It also entails punishment for those who deserve it. This system of rewarding and punishing ought to be carried out by those in power in accord with substantive and procedural rules. This raises the issue of whether those in power were elected to positions of power through fair processes and whether the system of reward and punishment is itself fair. Further, justice is not so much about equality as it is about equity. Thus, sometimes people should be treated equally and sometimes not. The three main types are retributive, compensatory, and distributive. Justice as retribution concerns fair punishment practices. Typically, in the discourse of ethics we refer to retribution in terms of accountability and the need to punish those who violate professional standards. Part of this involves exposing those who violate our common standards and agreements. Compensatory justice concerns fair reward practices. It is what we do when we settle on an equitable way of rewarding individuals for their achievements or benefiting others because of their disadvantages or for harms done to them. Finally, distributive justice concerns fair allocation practices. It concerns how the benefits and burdens of our community are passed out. In our community it concerns the allocation of protections, rights, goods, and services.  In my trans-humanist account I argue that we must extend this conception of justice to all life forms, not only to humans.  This is the shift in Archimedean point I advocate.

When we translate the value of justice into action we usually must make a comparison. We compare the actions, needs, or merits of one person to those of others. In order to assess what is fair we must assess what a person deserves by comparison him with others. We can only determine what is fair by determining what is fair to others. Thus, justice is always relative to the situation, persons, and resources at hand. Justice also requires equal treatment of those who are similarly situated and unequal treatment of those who are not similarly situated. In the attempt to be just we must presume that persons are equals unless reflective differences show that they are not. In order to demonstrate that persons are persons ought to be treated differently, for example with regard to job skills, we need to look at the job and determine which skills are necessary for that job.  This process takes proving that a skill is necessary, or is a crucial part of the task to be done and not just an accidental or irrelevant fact. For instance, a program that is testing candidates who are applying to become firefighters can prove that the skill of being able to carry 200 pounds is relevant to one’s performance as a firefighter. Thus it is just to treat unequally candidates who can carry 200 pounds and those who cannot.  I argue that justice must include the interests of all living beings not just humans.

In order to pursue justice we must overcome a concept of self that limits responsibility, which is the third value that we want to adopt. Responsibility is first that quality that makes us committed to anything. It requires that we follow through on the values that we have recognized as a basic part of what it means to be human and more specifically what it means to be a part of any particular group. When we are connected to other people we have responsibility to them. It is what makes us care about being ethical and perhaps can be spoken about as moral motivation. Responsibility is perhaps the most important value underpinning any moral transformation. Let’s therefore develop an extended and sustained discussion about it.  In order to prepare yourself for this discussion, imagine a social ontology—a set of expectations—that is not merely based on contract.  Let’s consider instead that it is based on my axiom of ontological parity.

Responsibility can be thought of in two senses. First, it is the precondition for being moral, that is, thinking that ethics is important in the first place. Second, it is the list of those specific actions required of us when we are responsible to or for someone or something. It is that which binds us to the world and to others, requiring a response when appropriate. When we are infants we do not understand responsibility; our only task it seems is to immediately satisfy our desires. As we grow older we recognize that our needs must be rank ordered and mediated by the needs of others. Responsibility manifests itself by reflecting on and acting upon the constellation of our whole value system. It is the very way that we can explain our connection to others. Further, it is the way that we connect to the world and to others–in terms of our value systems–that gives meaning to the lives of each of us.

Our specific responsibilities come in two ways. We are responsible to some others, for example our co-workers and supervisors, and we are responsible for some others, again including our co-workers or perhaps those who are on our work team. When we are responsible to someone we must render an accounting to that person, and we have duties to do so. These duties in fact come from the very nature of the relationship that we have presumably entered into freely. For example, a mailman has the duty to deliver the mail even though he may be tired or not feel well. A mother may have the duty to care for her children even though she may have other interests and desires. These responsibilities are accepted as a part of agreeing to do a particular job, whether or not we actually like or enjoy each and every one. In addition, those things that we are responsible for are those actions and events that we cause or have some causal relationship to because we are the moral agent who brings them about.

The word “responsibility” operates in at least two dimensions.  It contains a moral notion of personal culpability and a legal notion concerned with collective organization and the indemnification of victims. Individual moral responsibility is first concerned with imputation of blame because of an act that violates an obligation. To identify one as a perpetrator means to make him responsible for the consequences of an act. He answers for it because the action is attributed to him. Although sometimes responsibility is attributed to those who take initiative, thereby assigning them adulation, we usually speak of it in the negative sense, when someone wrongs another.

The negative usage comes from the criminal law, in which we assign a penalty to someone who is guilty of an offense. We show that a person has committed an act while in control of his faculties and assign him punishment in accordance with various factors, the most important of which is the attribution of responsibility for the act and its consequences. Responsibility establishes a three-part relationship between the responsible person, the domain of his responsibility, and the authority before which that person is answerable.

Legal responsibility implies an obligation to restore damage caused to others through one’s own fault and in criminal law to suffer the established penalty. In morality, as well as in law, the paradigm case involves an informed intentionality, or lack of regard for the interests of others. In the professional or occupational domain, the moral reference of responsibility for one’s actions is founded on the obligation not to harm others and to restore the injuries one has caused. It is an individualistic responsibility born out of the obligation to answer for one’s acts and to act in a way that any other person could act in a similar manner. Each professional role one plays comes with a certain set of duties, and a person thereby assumes responsibility for faithfully discharging the duties that come with the role. This notion also includes the ideal not to charge others for one’s own responsibility. It is very important to note that even if our behavior is highly constricted within the organization in which we work, we still cannot legitimately renounce our capacity for autonomous behavior. We always have choice.

What is very interesting is how modern technology and the rise of super- corporations has put into question the traditional notion of responsibility. In this new notion the fault of the origin of an accident is not emphasized. Instead, the focus is on restoring to the victim was taken from him. The increasing complexity of human action in modern industry, where there are often several structural, organizational, and individual contributing factors, makes it very difficult to assign blame to one specific person. The sheer complexity of our technology has, in some cases, made the identification of direct causal linkage a nearly impossible task. We see, then, in the post-modern era, a real solidarity—of a sort—in human action.   I question that this appearance of solidarity is real solidarity. In this new paradigm, employers pay heavily into insurance funds, which are in charge of paying damages to the wounded. We replace individual fault by social risk management at the managerial level, but this doesn’t alleviate the notion of responsibility at the individual level.

Solidarity creates a system in which one can be responsible without necessarily being guilty before the law. That is, individual responsibility persists, even though because of the complexity of the modern corporation in may be difficult if not impossible to assign legal blame for an accident or other malfeasance. Civil law, which insists on restoration, develops much quicker than criminal law, which is founded on penalty and on the pursuit of the perpetrator. Whereas criminal law and morality may often converge when determining the illicit act, civil law reinforces a disconnection from morality.

The notion of responsibility for risks develops a natural solidarity among the members of a particular community—the risk is shared collectively. This can create a tendency toward irresponsibility of workers, if companies are financially responsible through insurance, and this can create an economic counter-force against those workers. This necessitates a revival and a re-instantiation of individual worker responsibility through natural and matured solidarity. Because it is so difficult in some cases to assign individual culpability, we must at least consider the benefits of struggling together to deal with and overcome these complicated misfortunes–for they impact all of us and we suffer together, more or less.

In the new society, with its complicated industrial-technological complex, many sorts of human relations are no longer face-to-face. We affect others in the workplace, therefore, even though we do not see them. This could potentially lead to–and perhaps already has–a decreased sense of responsibility amongst individuals. This leads to the danger that the community itself will suffer the burden of taking care of the risks. In addition, we must also be on guard against the transfer of responsibility to those who are perceived as being responsible, for example, senior management, supervisors, and team leaders. This tendency here can lead to witch hunting of “those responsible,” who ultimately perhaps may answer for the negligence of others. In this regard, Taine himself claimed that: “The popular imagination needs living persons to whom it can impute its wrongs and on whom it can unload its emotions.” Here, restoration is viewed as insufficient, and punishment itself becomes the goal, in the attempt to purify society of the evil that threatens it. In this paradigm leaders are at risk as the body politic, including workers, members of professional organizations, business partners, students, family members, and more, each give up their own accountability.  As we use the Internet and other advanced communication technologies, we face the risk that this phenomenon may become more serious and more dangerous.

Nevertheless, behind the veil of anonymity there are real and actual persons who assume various responsibilities and who act them out in situation. The ones with more power and information have responsibility for the execution of tasks that have been entrusted to them and for the wellbeing of the persons for whom they care. While denying a direct causal relation–which is one of the characteristics of moral imputability–this responsibility dissociates itself from civil responsibility, which we have already viewed as a collective insurance. In this way, responsibility is understood as an emergent quality of playing a certain role.

In professional or occupational ethics, the level of responsibility of a particular person is correlative with the degree of power, knowledge, and liberty that are tied up with the part he or she plays within a certain organization and with the type of services they render. This often corresponds with a certain level of income and social power, as well. For persons who practice a profession–a doctor or a lawyer–moral obligations are strictly and clearly framed in terms of individual responsibility. Thus their acts are more easily understood than those of workers, whose power and behavior is always contextualized within a long chain of interaction and whose productive work cannot always been seen directly.

In addition, there are ways of administering human resources that reduce the responsibility of the agents involved, insistent as they are on obedience to instructions and subordination. This does not mean that the public or that the company itself does not look for a scapegoat in its workers, even though the actual tasks that they were responsible for were not substantial enough to have caused the malfeasance. We must always look at the organizational character, too, for some have rigid pyramidal structures and others have more cooperative and participatory, which allow for more expression of individual autonomy and responsibility.  This triggers the question about noetics, which can apply to individuals, to companies, to societies, and to whole cultures.  Because of these new complexities, some of which I have outlined, our responsibility forces us to consider our underlying philosophical anthropology, which affects individuals as it does the whole.  Let me be clear that this book here is a preparatory thinking about a new noetic foundation for the self, intersubjectivity, and the relations of humans to other life forms.

In a complex system in which everything is more entangled and more uncertain, it is important to acknowledge and promote the autonomy of those involved. This makes apparent the need for clarification of the role, power, and autonomy of each position in the web of relationships, which in turn creates a real ability to assign responsibility. Concomitant with this structural organization in which autonomies are created, we need a clear statement of standards of conduct, for each role to be discharged in the system. This set of ethical imperatives becomes a promise that each of us makes to each other, by playing the role that we agree to and to which we are assigned. Clearly, these promises need to be re-evaluated periodically, and we also must provide the sort of training and education that will enhance one’s ability to carry out his or her duties. In short, responsibilities must be clarified and the network of all interrelated responsibilities communicated in such a way that we all understand how our duties fit in with the whole.

Moreover, we must always be aware of changes in global conditions in all domains, including the economic, the governmental, the social, the legal, and so forth, which may transform relations of relative power in such a way as to create new zones of responsibility. These new zones of responsibility alter current moral relations as well as create new ones, thus we ought always be vigilant. Furthermore, we cannot ignore those who are distant from us either in space or in time. Just because we do not ever see someone, we may have moral responsibility to them because of the complex interrelationship of all things. That is, we may not be able to see all the consequences of our behavior even though we know that they exist. We ought also be careful about the future, for each action we engage in now has important effects for future generations. Hans Jonas expresses these concepts in this way: “Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life,” or “Act so that the effects of your action are not destructive of the future possibility of such life.”  This implies that we must act on right principle because we cannot see or understand the wide-ranging consequences of our behavior.

This new notion of responsibility orients itself toward the trajectory of our behavior and comports with the forgotten etymology of the word “responsible,” which is called sponsor in Latin. A sponsor vouches for someone else. To be responsible means to stand as a surety for another. For Nietzsche himself, being responsible means that one is capable of making promises, that is, giving one’s word, making a decision in which one commits oneself to the future. From this promise emerges behavior and one’s contribution toward the situation of others. Seen in this light, responsibility means that one is able to keep one’s promise. Concomitantly, it means to inspire confidence in others. Perhaps most importantly, it is about a lifetime exercise in virtue, in which we do work on ourselves, in relation to the others in our lives. At its very roots, then, freedom is mediated by responsibility to others because we are always in relation to them.

Let’s take stock of our account of responsibility. We must, first, always carefully consider the effects of our behavior on others, present and future. We must also take steps to prevent any foreseeable harm, before we act. Not to be aware of danger is irresponsible and thus we must live a life of preventative prudence. This obligation extends to all the domains of social life even where the causal links are harder to see. Second, we are witnessing an explosion of knowledge about our world, and this also mandates that we engage in reasonable research to discover potential harms. We must derivatively pay attention to the obligation to communicate both our knowledge and our lack of knowledge about any factors that may affect a risk of harm. The third obligation consists in restoring to victims what they lose, through the system of suretyship. Presumably this transfer of resources back to victims comes through channels of compensatory and even retributory justice to which we adhere and about which we dialogue, keeping firmly in mind that education and moral growth is the main objective.

Traditionally, ethical responsibility focused on antecedent causes and was mostly concerned with individual duties that emerged out of present and past relationships. This paradigm is giving way to a new focus toward the future and long-term relationships, especially pinpointing those individuals who are especially susceptible to the effects of collective action. We are moving from a mere system that prohibits us from actively harming other to a system in which we are responsible for proactively changing structures that harm and for actually helping others. We are, then, not just responsible for keeping our house in order. The watermark is higher, and now we are more and more responsible for others—those we supervise, the innocent, the weak, those in the future, and so forth. My responsibility no longer emanates from inside of me. Instead, it comes from each other person who calls to me, who appeals to me. I, in turn, must listen attentively so that I may hear their calls. I must look beyond my own immediate circle of relations and adopt a broader view, becoming responsible for a much wider range of individuals. It is not that we become responsible for everyone and everything. Yet, it means that we transform a duty-based ethics where we pursue the right action into the pursuit of virtue in which we pursue the good and are always on the look out for the needs and interests of others.  This includes all Others.

Let us now talk about becoming mature. Let us talk about the developmental process of assuming broader and deeper levels of responsibility. Before we are conscious we are beings with urges and wants. This is the state of a child, whose original urge is for self-directed happiness. We can characterize this wanting as selfish, narcissistic, with the logic of pursuing as much pleasure as possible and as avoiding as much pain as is possible. Here, the conscious subject thinks that he is the center of the world and the measure of all things. He is the center of all meaning and all claims to truth. This, we hold, is the unconscious narcissism that has determined the entire western vision of who we are. It is the basis for our anthropology of the subject, of the self.

In this state, we are so involved with ourselves that we view all other things in light of ourselves. We are shackled to our own self-image and find our wellbeing in the pleasure we have in our own image. At bottom our desires are directed right back toward ourselves as we each try to wrap our heads around the rest of the world, including other people. In this state, then, we totalize a world in terms of our own small frame of mind. Here there is a complete convergence between oneself and objective reality.  This lack of a gap or discrepancy is our propensity toward self-deception.  It is a denial of the transcendent, which is the world of possibility, of overcoming, and of change.  This foundation creates complacency, depression, and misplaced aggression.

This state prohibits us from directing ourselves toward another person in terms of his own difference. Rather, in this state we utilize the other’s image for our own project of becoming. In this kind of way of life, which is mostly unconscious, I want others to want me in various ways. This helps me develop my self-identity as well as my self-esteem. Yet if I approach others in this narcissistic way, only in terms of my own need for wholeness, I preclude myself from listening to their need. This way in the world creates a kind of tit-for-tat, competitive [and adversarial] social dynamic in which we do things for others in the hope and with the expectation that we will receive something in return. It creates a world that is a war of all against all, overtly or covertly.

Unfortunately, when we see others in this way, we often unconsciously attribute to them the qualities of ourselves. This externalizing of our own self creates a project of mastering the other when in reality we are just trying to master the wounds of the past that we have internalized into ourselves. This kind of need can also show up in the belief in a god that is narcissistic. In this state, we pursue a unity with god in order to obtain an overwhelming assurance and protected-ness. Again, though, in our narcissism we are only chasing ourselves.

Yet we realize that we can never reduce the other as a function of our own happiness. He is always different, and always escapes what we want from him. But in this egocentric involvement with the world, we create relations of power with other people. Because of the fear of losing our own identity in the face of the other, we try harder to ignore our difference, but in this way we don’t see what he may need from us. This creates a social world that is very much based on an economy of usefulness–we each see the other in terms of his or her use value. I use you in order to affirm and develop myself; you do the same; and so do we all.

 

All of us, led by our egocentrism, are motivated by our need for autonomy, wanting to expand the reach of our influence as much as possible, and thus we collide with each other in our everyday push for power. From this conflict the numerous people who inhabit the same ecosphere cannot each be at the center of things. This causes us–in our egocentricity–to position ourselves against each other. But hardly anyone wants to live in this kind of system, in which no one can be trusted and where we constantly have to watch our back. The better things in life–peace, music, relaxation, pleasure, and the like–don’t come when we are always on the verge of violence. As a consequence we enter into compacts with others, giving up only so much of our autonomy as is necessary to avoid the other’s violence. This leads to the formulation of laws and clear statements of rights.

The problem with this way of thinking is that it treats weaker groups and individuals unfairly. This is so because the system itself is born of egocentrism and relations of power. Within the logic of this system, attention is given to the powerless only to the extent that they pose a threat to the powerful. Our history, then, is a history of conquests; it is a humanism of those that are proud of being conquerors. Within a history of this kind of competitive dynamic–of all against all–we have become desensitized to the other, and the cycle intensifies. Most of us suffer a constantly nagging that something is wrong, but we hide from it; we run from it. We use food, drugs, sex, shopping, and the like to distract ourselves from the truth of our lack of attention to the other.  We thus retreat from our responsibility to others, each other, and all Others.

 

Nevertheless, at some point in our development, in our maturation process, we understand that we are not at the center of the social world and that we never were really. This presents us with the conceptual and experiential problem of finding a way out of our narcissism and our egocentrism. We cannot do it in terms of our own internalized, pleasure-seeking enterprise. It therefore must come from outside each one of us. It must come from the other himself. As such, we must transcend viewing the other as a force that must be overcome. Furthermore, we must see the other—not in terms of our own categories of understanding and not in terms of our own agenda—but in terms of his or her radical difference.

It is the look. The solution involves the look of the other. It is the other’s glance that breaks through my egocentric construction of him. When I look into the other’s face, directly in the eyes, I see how different he is. I can flee from this fact. I can hide it. But I know it. This is the fundamental fact in my interaction with the other. I know at some level that he always escapes me, always escapes my ideas about him. It is an uncanny feeling that we experience, as we realize that the other really is different. Just the look of the other resists my attempt to wrap my head around him. It is his plea for me not to annihilate him—not to kill him. That he is unfamiliar.

The face of the other becomes my judge. He raises the issue of my power. He raises the issue of his own difference. In the other’s face we recognize that what we take to be our right and our freedom is just an imperialism that conquers, that takes, and that murders. I realize that my spontaneous impulse toward self- affirmation and self-development is not so innocent, that I affect others from the ground up, even in my so-called reality as a free being. My conscience tells me from the bottom up that I am necessarily interdependent with others.  This includes all sentient life, including humans and other beings both known and unknown.

This responsibility that causes me shame precedes my ideas about freedom. It precedes any agreements I make. It has little to do with feelings of altruism or sympathy for others, feelings that come from conscious awareness. I learn that my responsibility comes as a very part of who I am. I learn that I am not independent from others and that I live for the other—one way or the other. I learn that I am not only responsible for my own “free” decisions but that I am also responsible for the other, and for his responsibility as well. Dostoevsky himself agrees with this extreme view of responsibility by saying in The Brothers Karamazov that “each of us is guilty before all, for all, and I more than all others.” I am thereby responsible for my neighbor. When the other looks at me, calls to me, I cannot avoid him. I cannot pretend that responsibility for him is not my concern for my pretending belies my acknowledgment, that I have heard his appeal. In the midst of the other’s face I realize that I do have a choice. I can either use him economically or answer to his appeal. If I answer his appeal, I act without regard for my desire. This goodness demands no repayment or satisfaction. Here, the concern for myself disappears from the center of attention. I become preoccupied with the other’s situation and the other’s need. I surpass my concern for my own life as I concentrate on what the other needs from me.  This responsibility extends to all humans, including the elderly, the weak, the infirm, and the disabled.  They each have a Look, and they each appeal no matter what their level of functioning.  They each play a part in the whole of humanity.  Moreover, there is no good reason to preclude other sentient beings from this responsibility.  If we extend the map of interdependency beyond human beings in order to include the biosphere as a whole we see that the interdependency goes beyond humanity, returns to it, and is informed by it.

Let us be clear that this a struggle: the choice between egocentrism and responsibility. Goodness comes every time I successfully free myself from my selfishness. I must constantly be vigilant to my natural tendency to put myself first. The other must always count for more. Perhaps goodness just is this struggle between narcissism and responsibility. This is not to say that I negate myself as a person or that I negate my own identity. Instead, it is a matter of putting the other first as a matter of course and as a reversal of spontaneous, selfish inclination. Giving to the other goes hand in hand with emptying myself of myself. Giving truly means giving something up. Giving means giving a gift of myself. When I am responsible I am for the other always, in spite of myself.

In this new paradigm, or way of being, I do not primarily seek out the protection of my own rights. Instead I seek out and advance the rights of others. I protect the other first. I serve the other first. I look out for the other first. I answer to the other first. I give to the other first. I give to the other without regard for my feeling. I give to the other without expectation of repayment. I give to the other without considering the potential advantages. In my giving, which is without regard for any instrumental good that I could achieve through my giving, I give universally and without discrimination. I give because it is my responsibility to do so. Thus, my relationship with the person to whom I give is not a relation to a particular other; instead it is a relation to all, distant and near. It is a universal stance.

When I am responsible to the other I am led by the truth that the other has a right over me. All others occupy this place in me, thus I must act in ways that protect even the absent others. It may that the only responsibility I have for the other is economic, for it is only through the economic relation that I can protect him.

This requires careful mediation between all my responsibilities to others, as well as to my responsibilities for my own self-development.  I must develop my abilities to serve others. Each of us, to whatever degree we are capable of must also, and especially if this is the role we are playing, make sure that the institutional structures that carry out justice are based on the kind of responsibility about which we have been talking. One can argue that this kind of a society is a utopian ideal but this is not a good reason for not trying to attain it. We must constantly charge ourselves to higher standards, as long as they keep us from drifting back into the kind of egocentrism that leads to the sort of violence and war that we see today.

Dr. Kevin Boileau

|
No Comments
Prof. Kevin Boileau

There are a number of points we at Freedom4Animals would like to make about the Zoo Director’s decision to choose the violent alternative in the zoo’s murder of Harambe, the innocent and imprisoned Gorilla.

First: Harambe never choose a life of imprisonment. Humans chose that for him. Because of that choice, we believe the Zoo owed him a fiduciary duty to protect his interests and his welfare always. The best choice would have been to send him to a sanctuary, but because the zoo chose to imprison him, the fiduciary duty follows.

Second: Because Harambe is a non-human primate he is not considered to be a “person” with due process, legal rights under the U.S. Constitution. Instead, under the “chattel” doctrine, he is considered to be property much like an orange or a chair, other than the enfeebled Animal Welfare Act which never protected him in a meaningful way. We find this intellectually dissatisfying because Harambe shares all the important traits that make humans human. He had a life plan; he had intention; he had moods; he was social; he required love and protection; he had autonomy and sentience.

Third: Many people are feeling outrage about the unjustified killing of Harambe because their morality diverges from what the law protects. They know something is intuitively wrong with the Zoo Director’s actions but they cannot articulate it in terms of rights and due process. Freedom4Animals will, therefore, speak for Harambe, our fallen cousin with DNA almost identical to ours.

Fourth: Humans base their legal rights on illusory and confusing notions about so-called natural rights. In reality, humans claim natural rights by fiat, and then find it easy to construct legal rights based on them. Within this worldview, humans always have greater ontological value than any other sentient and autonomous being. In cases of conflict humans, therefore, always win, and other beings always lose. This comes from the autonomous, acquisitive, possessive self of the Enlightenment, a philosophy that encourages humans to commodify everything and everyone around them, including non-human primates. In the case of Harambe, he was nothing more than a source of revenue to the North American system of zoos. The zoo director proved that on Saturday, the day after Harambe’s 17th birthday.

Fifth: We propose a new kind of human subjectivity that chooses a gentler and kinder orientation toward other sentient beings, and which assumes ontological parity with other primates. This new way in the world we call vivantonomy, which espouses a philosophy of vivantology. It would also grant all primates the same kind of rights that humans enjoy. In that case, someone would stand in for Harambe and due the zoo and the mother for negligence or worse, obtaining justice for this beautiful, innocent primate who was guilty of no malfeasance of any kind. Without this form of justice, we believe that we only continue a new kind of holocaust against non-human primates, much like Nazi Germany did against Jews. It has the same logic and motivation.

Sixth: We propose a primate rights bill that prevent this sort of murderous behavior by a zoo director and which would also seek justice in a court of law for its violation. The title of our book is a Prolegomenon toward a Primate Rights Bill, which is on amazon.com, authored by Nazarita Goldhammer and Prof. Kevin Boileau at Freedom4Animals, two scientist-philosophers who are working tirelessly for theoretical and practical possibilities for human transformation. Our goal is to utilize all revenue from the sales of this book to introduce federal legislation that will close zoos and other legislation that will protect a new due process right for the important interests of all primates, human or non-human.

Seventh: The Zoo never exercised its fiduciary duty to Harambe after its original counterpart falsely imprisoned him from the first day of his precious life. The Cincinnati Zoo designed an enclosure that was the structural and negligent cause of Harambe’s intentional killing and, in fact, it did not protect against the negligent acts of the boy’s mother. Then, after this systematic treatment of Harambe as a commodification—it chose the violent alternative. When the Director directed the killing, he proved the value of Harambe’s life to the Zoo and to the people of Cincinnati.  There were many choices along the way that would have better protected Harambe. Now, in the 13th hour of his life, he has no rights because he is a thing, no better than the feces of our capitalistic greed and our ignorance about the truth: Harambe was a person.

 

The question now is: What are we going to do about it?

 

Prof. Kevin Boileau

Co-Executive Director

Freedom4Animals

415.830.0065

No Comments